A Neo-Materialist Interpretation
by Manuel De Landa.
THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
The distinction between institutions which emerge from centralized
and decentralized decision-making by its human components has
come to occupy center-stage in several different contemporary
philosophies. Economist and Artificial Intelligence guru Herbert
Simon, for example, views bureaucracies and markets as the human
institutions which best embody these two conceptions of control. {1}
Hierarchical institutions are the easiest ones to analyze, since
much of what happens within a bureaucracy in planned by someone
of higher rank, and the hierarchy as a whole has goals and behaves
in ways that are more or less consistent with those goals. Markets,
on the other hand, are tricky. Indeed, the term "market"
needs to be used with care because it has been greatly abused
over the last century by theorists on the left and the right.
As Simon remarks, the term does not refer to the world of corporations,
whether monopolies or oligopolies, since in these commercial institutions
decision-making is highly centralized, and prices are set by command.
I would indeed limit the sense of the term even more to refer
exclusively to those weakly gatherings of people at a predefined
place in town, and not to a dispersed set of consumers catered
by a system of middleman (as when one speaks of the "market"
for personal computers). The reason is that, as historian Fernand
Braudel has made it clear, it is only in markets in the first
sense that we have any idea of what the dynamics of price formation
are. In other words, it is only in peasant and small town markets
that decentralized decision-making leads to prices setting themselves
up in a way that we can understand. In any other type of market
economists simply assume that supply and demand connect to each
other in a functional way, but they do not give us any specific
dynamics through which this connection is effected. {2} Moreover,
unlike the idealized version of markets guided by an "invisible
hand" to achieve an optimal allocation of resources, real
markets are not in any sense optimal. Indeed, like most decentralized,
self-organized structures, they are only viable, and since they
are not hierarchical they have no goals, and grow and develop
mostly by drift.
Herbert Simonis distinction between command hierarchies and decentralized
markets may turn out to be a special case of a more general dichotomy.
In the view of philosophers Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari,
this more abstract classes, which they call strata and self-consistent
aggregates (or trees and rhizomes), are defined not so much by
the locus of control, as by the nature of the elements that are
connected together. Strata are composed of homogenous elements,
whereas self-consistent aggregates, or to use the term I prefer,
meshworks, articulate heterogeneous elements as such. {3} For example,
a military hierarchy allocates people into internally homogenous
ranks before joining them together through a chain of command.
Markets, on the other hand, allow for a set of heterogeneous needs
and offers to become articulated through the price mechanism,
without reducing their diversity.
As both Simon and Deleuze and Guattari emphasize, the dichotomy
between hierarchies and markets, or more generally, between strata
and meshworks, should be understood in purely relative terms.
In the first place, in reality it is hard to find pure cases of
these two structures: even the most goal-oriented organization
will still show some drift in its growth and development, and
most markets even in small towns contain some hierarchical elements,
even if it is just the local wholesaler which manipulates prices
by dumping (or withdrawing) large amounts of a product on (or
from) the market. Moreover, hierarchies give rise to meshworks
and meshworks to hierarchies. Thus, when several bureaucracies
coexist (governmental, academic, ecclesiastic), and in the absence
of a super-hierarchy to coordinate their interactions, the whole
set of institutions will tend to form a meshwork of hierarchies,
articulated mostly through local and temporary links. Similarly,
as local markets grow in size, as in those gigantic fairs which
have taken place periodically since the Middle Ages, they give
rise to commercial hierarchies, with a money market on top, a luxury
goods market underneath and, after several layers, a grain market
at the bottom. A real society, then, is made of complex and changing
mixtures of these two types of structure, and only in a few cases
it will be easy to decide to what type a given institution belongs.
The dichotomy between strata and meshworks can be usefully applied
in a wide variety of contexts. For instance, animal species may
be considered biological instantiations of a stratified structure
while ecosystems may be treated as meshworks. This raises the
question of whether some (or most) of the applications of these
terms are purely metaphorical. There is, no doubt, some element
of metaphor in my use of the terms, but behind the appearance
of linguistic analogy there are, I believe, common physical processes
behind the formation of real meshworks and strata which make all
the different usages of the terms quite literal. These common
processes cannot be captured through linguistic representations
alone and we need to move to the realm of engineering diagrams
to specify them.
Perhaps a concrete example will help clarify this rather crucial
point. When we say (as Marxists used to say) that "class
struggle is the motor of history" we are using the word "motor"
in a purely metaphorical sense. However, when say that "a
hurricane is a steam motor" we are not simply making a
linguistic analogy: rather we are saying that hurricanes embody
the same diagram used by engineers to build steam motors, that
is, that it contains a reservoir of heat, that it operates via
thermal differences and that it circulates energy and materials
through a (so-called) Carnot cycle. Deleuze and Guattari use the
term "abstract machine" to refer to this diagram shared
by very different physical assemblages. Thus, there would be an
"abstract motor" with different physical instantiations
in technological objects and natural atmospheric processes.
What I would like to argue here is that there are also abstract
machines behind the structure-generating processes which yield
as historical products specific meshworks and hierarchies. Let
us begin by discussing the case of hierarchical structures, and
in particular, of social strata (classes, castes). The term "social
stratum" itself is clearly a metaphor, involving the idea
that just as geological strata are layers of rocky materials stacked
on top of each other so classes and castes are like layers of human
materials in which some are higher and some lower. Is it possible
to go beyond metaphor and show that the genesis of both geological
and social strata involve the same engineering diagram?. Geological
strata (accumulations of sedimentary rocks like sandstone or limestone)
are created through a process involving (at least) two distinct
operations. When one looks closely at the layers of rock in an
exposed mountain side, one striking characteristic is that each
layer contains further layers, each composed of small pebbles
which are nearly homogenous with respect to size, shape and chemical
composition. Since pebbles in nature do not come in standard sizes
and shapes, some kind of sorting mechanism needs to be involved
here, some specific device to take a multiplicity of pebbles of
heterogeneous qualities and distribute them into more or less uniform
layers.
Geologists have uncovered one such mechanism: rivers acting as
veritable hydraulic computers (or at least, sorting machines).
Rivers transport rocky materials from their point of origin (a
previously created mountain subject to erosion or weathering)
to the place in the ocean where these materials will accumulate.
In this process, pebbles of variable size, weight and shape tend
to react differently to the water transporting them. These different
reactions to moving water are what sorts the pebbles, with the
small ones reaching the ocean sooner than the large ones, for
example. Once the raw materials have been sorted out into more
or less homogenous groupings deposited at the bottom of the sea
(that is, once they have become sedimented ), a second operation
is necessary to transform these loose collections of pebbles into
an entity of a higher scale: a sedimentary rock. This operation
consists in cementing the sorted components together into a new
entity with emergent properties of its own, that is, properties
such as overall strength and permeability that cannot be ascribed
to the sum of the individual pebbles. This second operation is
carried out by certain substances dissolved in water (such as
silica or hematite in the case of sandstones) which penetrate
the sediment through the pores between pebbles. As this percolating
solution crystallizes, it consolidates the pebble's temporary
spatial relations into a more or less permanent "architectonic"
structure. {4}
Thus, a double operation, a "double articulation" gets
us from structures at one scale to structures at another scale.
Deleuze and Guattari call these two operations "content"
and "expression" , and warn us against confusing them
with the old philosophical distinction between "substances"
and "forms". The reason is that each one of the two
articulations involves substances and forms: sedimentation is
not just about accumulating pebbles (substance) but also about
sorting them into uniform layers (form); while consolidation
not only effects new architectonic couplings between pebbles (form)
but also yields a new entity, a sedimentary rock (substance).
Moreover, these new entities may themselves accumulate and sort
(as in the alternating layers of schist and sandstone that make
up Alpine mountains) and become consolidated when tectonic forces
cause the accumulated layers of rock to fold and become a higher
scale entity, a mountain. {5}
In the model proposed by Deleuze and Guattari these two operations
constitute an engineering diagram and therefore we can expect
to find this "abstract machine of stratification" not
only in the world of geology, but also in the organic and human
worlds. For example, according to neo-Darwinism species form through
the slow accumulation of genetic materials, and of the adaptive
anatomical and behavioral traits that those genetic materials
yield when combined with nonlinear dynamical processes (such as
the interaction of cells during the development of an embryo).
Genes, of course, do not merely deposit at random but are sorted
out by a variety of selection pressures which include climate,
the action of predators and parasites and the effects of male
or female choice during mating. Thus, in a very real sense, genetic
materials "sediment" just as pebbles do, even if the
nonlinear dynamical system which performs the sorting operation
is completely different in detail. Furthermore, these loose collections
of genes can (like accumulated sand) be lost under some drastically
changed conditions (such as the onset of an Ice age) unless they
become consolidated together. This second operation is performed
by "reproductive isolation": when a given subset of
a population becomes incapable of mating with the rest (or as
in the case of horses and donkeys, when their offspring are sterile).
Reproductive isolation acts as a "ratchet mechanism"
which conserves the accumulated adaptation and makes it impossible
for a given population to "de-evolve" all the way back
to unicellular organisms. Through selective accumulation and isolative
consolidation, individual animals and plants come to form a higher
scale entity: a new species. {6}
We can also find these two operations (and hence, this abstract
diagram) in the formation of social classes. We talk of "social
strata" whenever a given society presents a variety of differentiated
roles to which not everyone has equal access, and when a subset
of those roles (i.e. those to which a ruling elite alone has access)
involves the control of key energetic and material resources.
While role differentiation may be a spontaneous effect of an intensification
in the flow of energy through society (e.g. as when a Big Man
in pre-State societies acts as an intensifier of agricultural
production ), the sorting of those roles into ranks along a scale
of prestige involves specific group dynamics. In one model, for
instance, members of a group who have acquired preferential access
to some roles begin to acquire the power to control further access
to them, and within these dominant groups criteria for sorting
the rest of society into sub-groups begin to crystallize. "It
is from such crystallization of differential evaluation criteria
and status positions that some specific manifestations of stratification
and status differences -such as segregating the life-styles of
different strata, the process of mobility between them, the steepness
of the stratificational hierarchies, some types of stratum consciousness,
as well as the degree and intensity of strata conflict- develops
in different societies." {7}
However, even though most societies develop some rankings of this
type, not in all of them do they become an autonomous dimension
of social organization. In many societies differentiation of
the elites is not extensive (they do not form a center while the
rest of the population forms an excluded periphery), surpluses
do not accumulate (they may be destroyed in ritual feasts), and
primordial relations (of kin and local alliances) tend to prevail.
Hence a second operation is necessary beyond the mere sorting of
people into ranks for social classes or castes to become a separate
entity: the informal sorting criteria need to be given a theological
interpretation and a legal definition, and the elites need to
become the guardians and bearers of the newly institutionalized
tradition, that is, the legitimizers of change and delineators
of the limits of innovation. In short, to transform a loose accumulation
of traditional roles (and criteria of access to those roles) into
a social class, the latter needs to become consolidated via theological
and legal codification. {8}
My main point can then be stated as follows: sedimentary rocks,
species and social classes (and other institutionalized hierarchies)
are all historical constructions, the product of definite structure-generating
processes which take as their starting point a heterogeneous collection
of raw materials (pebbles, genes, roles), homogenize them through
a sorting operation and then give the resulting uniform groupings
a more permanent state through some form of consolidation. Hence,
while some elements remain different (e.g. only human institutions,
and perhaps, biological species, involve a hierarchy of command)
others stay the same: the articulation of homogenous components
into higher-scale entities. (And all this, without metaphor ).
What about meshworks?. Deleuze and Guattari also offer a hypothetical
diagram for this type of structure, but its elements are not as
straightforward as those involved in the formation of strata.
For this reason I will begin the description of this other abstract
machine with some remarks about what mathematical and computer
models of meshworks have revealed about their formation and behavior,
and then attempt to derive their engineering diagram. Perhaps
the best studied type of meshwork is the so called "autocatalytic
loop", a closed chain of chemical processes involving not
only self-stimulation but also self-maintenance, that is, interconnecting
a series of mutually-stimulating pairs into a structure which
reproduces as a whole: a product that accumulates due to the catalytic
acceleration of one chemical reaction serves as the catalyst for
yet another reaction which, in turn, generates a product which
catalyses the first one. Hence, the loop becomes self-sustaining
as long as its environment contains enough raw materials for the
chemical reactions to proceed.
Francisco Varela and Humberto Maturana, pioneers in the study
of autocatalytic loops (e.g. their theory of "autopoeisis")
mention two general characteristics of these closed circuits:
they are dynamical systems which endogenously generate their own
stable states (called "attractors" or "eigenstates"),
and they grow and evolve by drift. . {9} An example of the first
characteristic are some chemical reactions involving autocatalysis
(as well as cross-catalysis) which function as veritable "chemical
clocks", in which the accumulation of materials from the
reactions alternate each other at perfectly regular intervals
. This rhythmic behavior is not imposed to the system from the
outside but generated spontaneously from within (via an attractor).
{10}
The second characteristic mentioned by Varela and Maturana, growth
by drift, may be explained as follows. In the simplest autocalytic
loops there are only two reactions, each producing a catalyst
for the other. But once this basic two-node network establishes
itself, new nodes may insert themselves into the mesh as long
as they do not jeopardize its internal consistency. Thus, a new
chemical reaction may appear (using previously neglected raw materials
or even waste products from the original loop) which catalyses
one of the original ones and is catalyzed by the other, so that
the loop now becomes a three-node network. The meshwork has now
grown but in a direction which is, for all practical purposes,
"unplanned". A new node (which just happens to satisfy
some internal consistency requirements) is added and the loop
complexifies, yet precisely because the only constraints were
internal, the complexification does not take place in order for
the loop as a whole to meet some external demand (such as adapting
to a specific situation). The surrounding environment, as source
of raw materials, certainly constraints the growth of the meshwork
but more in a proscriptive way (what not to do) than in a prescriptive
one (what to do). {11}
The question now is whether from these and other empirical studies
of meshwork behavior we can derive a structure-generating process
which is abstract enough to operate in the worlds of geology,
biology and human society. In the model proposed by Deleuze and
Guattari, there are three elements in this diagram. First, a set
of heterogeneous elements is brought together via an articulation
of superpositions , that is, an interconnection of diverse but
overlapping elements. (In the case of autocatalytic loops, the
nodes in the circuit are joined to each other by their functional
complementarities ). Second, a special class of operators, or
intercallary elements, is needed to effect this interlock via
local connections. (In our case, this is the role played by catalysts,
inserting themselves between two other chemical substances to
facilitate their interaction). Finally, the interlocked heterogeneities
must be capable of endogenously generating stable patterns of
behavior (for example, patterns at regular temporal or spatial
intervals.) {12} Is it possible to find instances of these three
elements in all different spheres of reality?
Besides the sedimentary type there exists another great class
of rocks called "igneous rocks" (such as granite) which
are the outcome of a radically different process of construction.
Granite forms directly out of a cooling magma, a viscous fluid
made out of a diversity of molten materials. Each of these liquid
components has a different threshold of crystallization, that
is, each undergoes the bifurcation towards the solid state at
a different critical point in temperature. This means that as
the magma cools down its different elements will separate as
they crystallize in sequence, those that solidify earlier serving
as containers for those which acquire a crystal form later. In
these circumstances the result is a complex set of heterogeneous
crystals which interlock with one another, and this is what gives
granite its superior strength. {13}
The second element in the diagram, intercallary elements, must
be defined more generally than just as catalytic substances, to
include anything which brings about local articulations from within,
"densifications, intensifications, reinforcements, injections,
showerings , like so many intercallary events". {14} The
reactions between liquid magma and the walls of an already crystallized
component, nucleation events within the liquid which initiate
the next crystallization, and even certain "defects"
inside the crystals (called "dislocations") which promote
growth from within, are all examples of intercallary elements.
Finally, chemical reactions within the magma may also generate
endogenous stable states.
When a reaction like the one involved in chemical clocks is not
stirred, the temporal intervals generated become spatial intervals,
forming beautiful spiral and concentric circle patterns which
sometimes can be observed in frozen form in some igneous rocks.
{15}
Thus, granite (as much as a fully formed autocatalytic loop) is
an instance of a meshwork, or in the terms used by Deleuze and
Guattari, of a self-consistent aggregate. Unlike Varela and Maturana,
for whom this quality of self-consistency exists only in the biological
and linguistic worlds, for Deleuze and Guattari "consistency,
far from being restricted to complex life forms, fully pertains
even to the most elementary atoms and particles". {16} Therefore
we may say that much as hierarchies (organic or social) are special
cases of a more abstract class, "strata", so autocatalytic
loops are special cases of "self-consistent aggregates".
And much as strata are defined as an articulation of homogenous
elements (and do not involve more specific features of hierarchies
such as having a chain of command), so self-consistent aggregates
are defined by their articulation of heterogeneous elements and
do not necessarily involve other, less general, features (such
as growth by drift or internal autonomy). Let us now give some
biological and cultural examples of the way in which the diverse
may be articulated as such via self-consistency.
As I just mentioned, a species (or more precisely, the gene pool
of a species) is a prime example of an organic stratified structure.
Similarly, an ecosystem represents a biological realization of
a self-consistent aggregate. While a species may be a very homogenous
structure (specially if selection pressures have driven many genes
to fixation) an ecosystem links together a wide variety of heterogeneous
elements (animals and plants of different species) which are articulated
through interlock, that is, by their functional complementarities.
Given that the main feature of an ecosystem is the circulation
of energy and matter in the form of food, the complementarities
in question are alimentary: prey-predator or parasite-host are
two of the most common functional couplings that make up food
webs. In this situation, symbiotic relations can act as intercallary
elements aiding the process of building food webs, with the most
obvious example being the bacteria that live in the guts of many
animals and which allow those animals to digest their food. Since
food webs also display endogenously generated stable states, all
three components of the abstract diagram seem to be realized in
this case.
I have already mentioned that markets may be considered examples
of cultural meshworks. In many cultures weekly markets have traditionally
been the meeting place for people with heterogeneous needs and
offers. Matching complementary demands (that is, interlocking
these people together by their needs and offers) is an operation
which is performed automatically by the price mechanism. (Prices
transmit not only information about the relative monetary value
of different products, but also incentive to buy and sell). All
that is needed for this automatic mechanism to work is that prices
drop in the face of an excess supply and that quantities produced
and offered decline when prices are lowered.
Of course, for this to work prices must set themselves, and therefore
we must imagine that there is not a wholesaler in town who can
manipulate prices by dumping (or hoarding) large amounts of a
given product into the market. In the absence of price manipulation,
money (even primitive money such as salt, shells or cigarettes)
performs the function of intercallary element: while with pure
barter the possibility of two exactly matching demands meeting
by chance is very low, with money those chance encounters become
unnecessary, and complementary demands may find each other at a
distance, so to speak. Finally, markets also seem to generate
endogenous stable states, particularly when commercial towns form
trading circuits, as can be seen in the cyclic behavior of their
prices.
Thus, much as sedimentary rocks, biological species and social
hierarchies are all particular cases of a stratified system (that
is, they are all historical products of a process of double articulation),
so igneous rocks, ecosystems and markets are self-consistent aggregates
(or meshworks), the result of the coming together and interlocking
of heterogeneous elements. This conception of very specific abstract
machines governing a variety of structure-generating processes
not only blurs the distinction between the natural and the artificial,
but also that between the living and the inert. It indeed points
towards a new form of materialist philosophy in which raw matter-energy
through a variety of self-organizing processes and an intense
power of morphogenesis, generates all the structures that surround
us. Furthermore, the structures generated cease to be the primary
reality, and matter-energy flows now acquire this special status.
From the point of view of the nonlinear dynamics of our planet,
the thin rocky crust on which we live and which we call our land
and home is perhaps its least important component. Indeed, if
we waited long enough, if we could observe planetary dynamics
at geological time scales, the rocks and mountains which define
the most stable and durable traits of our reality would dissolve
into the great underground lava flows of which they are but temporary
hardenings. Indeed, given that it is just a matter of time for
any one rock or mountain to be reabsorbed into the self-organized
flows of lava driving the dynamics of the lithosphere, these geological
structures represent a local slowing-down in this flowing reality.
It is almost as if every part of the mineral world could be defined
by specifying its chemical composition and its speed of flow :
very slow for rocks, faster for lava.
Similarly, our individual bodies and minds are mere coagulations
or decelerations in the flows of biomass, genes, memes and norms.
Here too we would be defined both by the materials we are temporarily
binding or chaining into our organic bodies and cultural minds,
as well as by the time scale of the binding operation. Given long
enough time scales, it is the flow of biomass through food webs
that matters, as well as the flow of genes through generations,
and not the bodies and species that emerge in these flows. Given
long enough time scales, our languages are also momentary slowing-downs
or thickenings in a flow of norms that can give rise to a multitude
of different structures. The overall world-view that this "geological
philosophy" generates may be put into a nut shell by introducing
some special technical terminology.
First of all, the fact that meshworks and hierarchies occur mostly
in mixtures, makes it convenient to have a label to refer to these
changing combinations. If the hierarchical components of the mix
dominate over the meshwork ones we may speak of a highly stratified
structure, while the opposite combination will be referred to
as one with a low degree of stratification. Moreover, since
meshworks give rise to hierarchies and hierarchies to meshworks,
we may speak of a given mixture as undergoing processes of destratification
as well as restratification, as its proportions of homogenous
and heterogeneous components change. Finally, since according to
this way of viewing things what truly defines the real world are
neither uniform strata nor variable meshworks but the unformed
and unstructured morphogenetic flows from which these two derive,
it will also be useful to have a label to refer to this special
state of matter-energy-information, to this flowing reality animated
from within by self-organizing processes constituting a veritable
non-organic life : the Body without Organs (BwO):
"The organism is not at all the body, the BwO; rather it
is a stratum on the BwO, in other words, a phenomenon of accumulation,
coagulation, and sedimentation that, in order to extract useful
labor from the BwO, imposes upon it forms, functions, bonds, dominant
and hierarchized organizations, organized trascendences...the
BwO is that glacial reality where the alluvions, sedimentations,
coagulations, foldings, and recoilings that compose an organism
-and also a signification and a subject- occur. " {17}
The label itself is, of course, immaterial and insignificant.
We could as well refer to this cauldron of non-organic life by
a different name. (Elsewhere, for instance, I called it the "machinic
phylum"). {18} Unlike the name, however, the referent of
the label is of extreme importance, since the flows of lava, biomass,
genes, memes, norms, money (and many others) are crucial for the
emergence of just about any stable structure that we cherish and
value (or, on the contrary, that oppresses and slaves us). We
could define the BwO in terms of this unformed, destratified flows,
as long as we keep in mind that what counts as destratified at
any given time and space scale is entirely relative. The flow
of genes and biomass are "unformed" if we compare them
to any given individual organism, but they themselves have internal
forms and functions. Indeed, if instead of taking a planetary
perspective we adopted a properly cosmic viewpoint, our entire
planet (together with its flows) would itself be a mere provisional
hardening in the vast flows of plasma which permeate the universe.
Human history has involved a variety of Bodies without Organs.
First, the sun, that giant sphere of plasma which intense flow
of energy drives most processes of self-organization in our planet,
and in the form of grain and fossil fuel, in our civilizations.
Second, the body of lava "conveyor belts" (convection
cells) which drive plate tectonics and which are responsible for
the most general geopolitical features of our planet, such as
the breakdown of Pangea into our current continents, and the subsequent
distribution of domesticable species, a distribution that benefited
Eurasia over the rest of the world. Third, the BwO constituted
by the coupled dynamics of the Hydrosphere/Atmosphere, and their
wild variety of self-organized entities: hurricanes, tsunamis,
pressure blocks, cyclones, and wind circuits. (The conquest of
the wind circuits of the Atlantic, the trade winds and the westerlies,
is what allowed the transformation of the American continent into
a vast supply zone to fuel the growth of the European urban economy).
Fourth, the genetic BwO constituted by the more or less free flow
of genes through microorganisms (via plasmids and other vectors),
which unlike the more stratified genetic flow in animals and plants,
has avoided human control even after the creation of antibiotics.
Fifth, those portions of the flow of solar energy through ecosystems
(flesh circulating in natural food webs) which have escaped urbanization,
particularly animal and vegetable weeds or rhizomes (The BwO formed
by underground rodent cities, for example). Finally, our languages,
when they formed dialect continua and circumstances conspired
to remove any stratifying pressure, also formed a BwO, as when
the Norman invaders imposed French as the language of the elites
allowing the peasant masses to create the English language out
of an amorphous soup of Germanic norms with Scandinavian spices.
Immanent to the BwO are a set of abstract machines, engineering
diagrams capturing the dynamics of certain structure-generating
processes. The two most general may be those behind the formation
of strata and self-consistent aggregates. But there are others.
For instance, when the sorting device is coupled with the ability
to replicate with variation, a new abstract machine emerges, this
time a blind probe head or searching device, capable of exploring
a space of possible forms. These abstract machines may be viewed
as equipped with "knobs" controlling certain parameters
which in turn define the dynamical state for the structure-generating
process, and hence, the nature of the generated structures themselves.
Key parameters include those controlling the strength and thoroughness
of the sorting process and the degree of consolidation or reproductive
isolation for the double-articulation machine; or the degrees
of temperature, pressure, volume, speed, density, connectivity
that play the role of control parameters generating the stable
states in meshworks; or the rates of mutation and recombination
which define the speed of the probe head, as well as the strength
of biomass flow and of the coupling between coevolving species,
which define the kind of space that the searching device explores.
Hence, using these abstract diagrams to represent what goes on
in the BwO is equivalent to using a system of representation in
terms of intensities, since it is ultimately the intensity of
each parameter that determines the kind of dynamic involved, and
hence, the character of the structures that are generated. Indeed,
one way of picturing the BwO is as that "glacial" state
of matter-energy-information which results from turning all these
knobs to zero , that is, to the absolute minimum value of intensity,
bringing all production of structured form to a halt:
"A BwO is made in such a way that it can be occupied, populated
only by intensities. Only intensities pass and circulate. Still,
the Bwo is not a scene, a place, or even a support upon which
something comes to pass... It is not space, nor is it in space;
it is matter that occupies space to a given degree -to the degree
corresponding to the intensities produced. It is nonstratified,
unformed, intense matter, the matrix of intensity, intensity=0
... Production of the real as an intensive magnitude starting
at zero." {19}
I must end now this brief exploration of what a Neo-Materialist
interpretation of the philosophy of Deleuze and Guattari would
be like. No doubt much detail has been left out. I like to think
of my interpretation as a kind of "pidginization" of
their complex ideas, followed by a "creolization" along
original lines. It nevertheless retains its basic geological spirit,
a philosophical stance which rejects ideas of progress not only
in human history but in natural history as well. Living creatures,
according to this stance, are in no way "better" than
rocks. Indeed, in a nonlinear world in which the same basic processes
of self-organization take place in the mineral, organic and cultural
spheres, perhaps rocks hold some of the keys to understand sedimentary
humanity, igneous humanity and all their mixtures.
{1} Herbert Simon. The Sciences of the Artificial. (MIT Press,
1994). p. 32-36
{2} Fernand Braudel. The Wheels of Commerce. (Harper and Row,
New York, 1986). p. 28-47
For the idea that "invisible hand" economics simply
assumes that demand and supply cancel each other out (i.e. that
markets clear) without ever specifying the dynamics that lead
to this state see:
Philip Mirowsky. More Heat than Light. Economics as Social Physics,
Physics as Nature is Economics. (Cambridge University Press, New
York 1991). p. 238-241
Mirowsky shows how the concept of the concept of the "invisible
hand" was formalized in the nineteenth century by simply
copying the form of equilibrium thermodynamics (Hence, in his
opinion, this branch of physics provided more heat than light).
He also warns that recent attempts to apply Prigogineis theories
to economics are doing the same thing, for example, assuming
the existence of attractors without specifying just what it is
that is being dissipated (i.e. only energetically dissipative
or "lossy" systems have attractors). See:
Philip Mirowsky. From Mandelbrot to Chaos in Economic Theory.
In Southern Economic Journal. Vol. 57, October 1990). p. 302
{3} Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. (University
of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1987). p. 335
"Stating the distinction in its more general way, we could
say that it is between stratified systems or systems of stratification
on the one hand, and consistent, self-consistent aggregates on
the other... There is a coded system of stratification whevever,
horizontally, there are linear causalities between elements; and,
vertically, hierarchies of order between groupings; and, holding
it all together in depth, a succession of framing forms, each
of which informs a substance and in turn serves as a substance
for another form. [e.g. the succession pebbles-sedimentary rocks-folded
mountains, footnote#5 below]... On the other hand, we may speak
of aggregates of consistency when instead of a regulated succession
of forms-substances we are presented with consolidations of very
heterogeneous elements, orders that have been short-circuited or
even reverse causalities, and captures between materials and forces
of a different nature... ".
{4} Harvey Blatt, Gerard Middleton, Raymond Murray. Origin of
Sedimentary Rocks. (Prentice Hall, New Jersey, 1972). p.102 and
353
{5} Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. op.
cit. p. 41
Actually, here Deleuze and Guattari incorrectly characterize the
two articulations involved in rock-production as "sedimentation-folding".
The correct sequence is "sedimentation-cementation".
Then, at a different spatial scale , "cyclic sedimentary
rock accumulation-folding into mountain". In other words,
they collapse two different double-articulations (one utilizing
as its starting point the products of the previous one), into
one. I believe this correction does not affect their underlying
argument, and that indeed, it strenghtens it.
{6} Niles Eldridge. Macroevolutionary Dynamics. Species, Niches
and Adaptive Peaks. (MacGraw Hill, New York 1989). p. 127
{7} S.N. Eisenstadt. Continuities and Changes in Systems of Stratification.
In Stability and Social Change. Bernard Barber and Alex Inkeles,
eds. (Little Brown, Boston 1971). p. 65
{9} Humberto R. Maturana and Francisco J. Varela. The Tree of
Knowledge. The Biological Roots of Human Understanding. (Shambhala,
Boston 1992). p. 47 and 115.
Other researchers have discovered that as the loop adds new nodes
it may reach a critical threshold of complexity and undergo a
bifurcation, a transition to a new state where complexification
accelerates. Since the states to which a phase transition leads
are in no way "directed" or "progressive",
changing and developing by crossing bifurcations is another way
of growing by drift.
{10} Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers. Order out of Chaos.
op.cit.. p. 147
{11} Francisco J. Varela. Two Principles of Self-Organization.
In Self-Organization and Management of Social Sytems. H. Ulrich,
G.J.B. Probst eds. (Springer Verlag, Berlin 1984) p. 27
{12} Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. op.cit.
p.329
{13} Michael Bisacre. Encyclopedia of the Earthis Resources. (Exeter
Books, New York 1984). p. 79
{14} Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari. ibid. p. 328
The authors constantly refer to catalysis in their theories of
meshwork-like structures (rhizomes, smooth spaces etc.) They tend
sometimes to view catalysis in terms on one specific (albeit very
important) type of catalysts: the allosteric enzymes discovered
by Jaques Monod, which are like programmable catalysts, with two
heads:
What is needed here is to make the notion of a "catalyst"
more abstract so that the specific functions of a chemical catalyst
(to perform acts of recognition via a lock and key mechanism,
to accelerate or decelerate chemical reactions) are not what matters,
but the more general notion of aiding growth "from within"
or "from in-between". One step in this direction has
been taken by Arthur Iberall (a pioneer in the application of
ideas from nonlinear dynamics to human history), by defining catalytic
activity as the ability to force a dynamical system from one attractor
to another. In the case of a chemical catalyst the dynamical system
would be the target molecule (the one to be catalyzed) and the
two stable states would be its "unreactive" and "reactive"
states, so that by switching them from one to another the catalyst
accelerates the reaction. See:
Elsewhere, Iberall notes that in this sense, nucleation events
and dislocations may be considered to involve "acts of catalysis".
Nucleation refers to the process through which the structures
which appear after a phase transition (crystals just after the
bifurcation to the solid state, for example) consolidate and grow,
as opposed to reverting back to the previous state. (By crossing
the bifurcation in the opposite direction). Typically, something
has to catalyze the growth of structure to a critical mass (nucleation
threshold) after which growth may proceed more or less spontaneously.
This "something" may be anything from a dust particle
to a defect in the container in which the crystallization is happening.
If one carefully removes all particles and defects one can indeed
cool down a liquid past the bifurcation point without crystallization
taking place. (Eventually, as we cool down further, even a microscopic
thermal fluctuation can act as catalyst an trigger the nucleation).
Dislocations , on the other hand, are line defects within the
body of the growing crystals which help them grow by storing mechanical
energy in their misaligned (hence nonequilibrium) composing atoms.
This stored energy allows them to promote crystal growth by lowering
nucleation thresholds. Thus, in this abstract sense of "catalysis"
the intercallary events involved in the creation of igneous rocks
are of the meshwork-generating type. On this see:
Arthur Iberall. Toward a General Science of Viable Systems. (McGrall-Hill,
1972). p. 208
But we can go further. Defined this way, "catalysis"
becomes a true abstract operation: anything that switches a dynamical
system (an interacting population of molecules, ants, humans
or institutions) from one stable state to another is literally
a catalyst in this sense. Hence, we may use this definition
not only to move down from chemistry (the field of the literal
application of the term) to physics without metaphor, but also
up, to biology, sociology, linguistics. Cities and institutions,
for example, would be instanciations of this operator to the extent
that they arise form matter-energy flows and decision-making processes,
but then react back on these flows and processes to constrain
them in a variety of ways (stimulating them or inhibiting them).
On the other hand, as Iberall himself notes, catalytic constraints
may combine with one another and form language-like systems. Another
physicist, Howard Pattee, has further elaborated the notion of
enzymes (organic catalysts) as syntactical constraints, operating
on a semantic world defined by its stable states.
On biological catalysts as syntactic constraints see:
{15} Gregoire Nicolis and Ilya Prigogine. Exploring Complexity.
(W.H. Freeman, New York 1989). p. 29
{16} Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari. ibid. p. 335
{17} Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. op.
cit. p.159
{18} While the term "Body Without Organs" was first
used in a philosophical context by Deleuze (borrowing from Artaud),
the almost synonymous "machinic phylum" seems to have
been coined and first used bt Guattari, in:
Felix Guattari. The Plane of Consistency. In Molecular Revolution.
(Penguin Books, New York 1984). p. 120
I do not claim that the two terms are strictly synonymous (although
I myself do use them that way). Rather what seems to be happening
is that these philosophers instead of building one theory are
attempting to create a meshwork of theories, that is, a set of
partially overlapping theories. Hence, key (near synonymous) concepts
(BWO, phylum, smooth space, rhizome) do not exactly coincide in
meaning but are slightly displaced from one another to create
this overlapping effect. The point remains that it is the referents
of these labels that matter and not the labels themselves.
References:
"... what holds heterogeneities together without their ceasing
to be heterogeneous ... are intercallary oscillations, synthesizers
with a least two heads." ibid. 329
Arthur Iberall and Harry Soodak. A Physics for Complex Systems.
In Self-Organizing Systems. The Emergence of Order. Eugene Yates
ed. (Plenum Press, New York 1987). p. 509
Howard Pattee. Instabilities and Information in Biological Self-Organization.
In Self-Organizing Systems. op. ed. p. 334