by Manuel De Landa.
MARKETS AND ANTIMARKETS
IN THE WORLD ECONOMY
One of the most significant epistemological events in recent years
is the growing importance of historical questions in the ongoing
reconceptualization of the hard sciences. I believe it is not
an exaggeration to say that in the last two or three decades, history
has almost completely infiltrated physics, chemistry and biology.
It is true that nineteenth century thermodynamics had already
introduced an arrow of time into physics, and hence the idea of
irreversible historical processes. It is also true that the theory
of evolution had already shown that animals and plants were not
embodiments of eternal essences but piecemeal historical constructions,
slow accumulations of adaptive traits cemented together via reproductive
isolation. However, the classical versions of these two theories
incorporated a rather weak notion of history into their conceptual
machinery: both thermodynamics and Darwinism admitted only one
possible historical outcome, the reaching of thermal equilibrium
or of the fittest design. In both cases, once this point was reached,
historical processes ceased to count. For these theories, optimal
design or optimal distribution of energy represented, in a sense,
an end of history.
Hence, it should come as no surprise that the current penetration
of science by history has been the result of advances in these
two disciplines. Ilya Prigogine revolutionized thermodynamics
in the 1960's by showing that the classical results were only
valid for closed systems where the overall amounts of energy are
always conserved. If one allows energy to flow in and out of a
system, the number and type of possible historical outcomes greatly
increases. Instead of a unique and simple equilibrium, we now
have multiple ones of varying complexity (static, periodic and
chaotic attractors); and moreover, when a system switches from
one to another form of stability (at a so-called bifurcation),
minor fluctuations can be crucial in deciding the actual form
of the outcome. Hence, when we study a given physical system,
we need to know the specific nature of the fluctuations that have
been present at each of its bifurcations, in other words, we need
to know its exact history to understand its current dynamical
form. {1}
And what is true of physical systems is all the more so for biological
ones. Attractors and bifurcations are features of any system in
which the dynamics are nonlinear, that is, in which there are
strong interactions between variables. As biology begins to include
these nonlinear dynamical phenomena in its models, for example,
in the case of evolutionary arms-races between predators and prey,
the notion of a "fittest design" loses its meaning.
In an arms-race there is no optimal solution fixed once and for
all, since the criterion of fitness itself changes with the dynamics.
This is also true for any adaptive trait which value depends on
how frequent it occurs in a given population, as well as in cases
like migration, where animal behavior interacts nonlinearly with
selection pressures. As the belief in a fixed criterion of optimality
disappears from biology, real historical processes come to reassert
themselves once more. {2}
Computers have played a crucial role in this process of infiltration.
The nonlinear equations that go into these new historical models
cannot be solved by analytical methods alone, and so scientists
need computers to perform numerical simulations and discover the
behavior of the solutions. But perhaps the most crucial role
of digital technology has been to allow a switch from a purely
analytic, top-down style of modeling, to a more synthetic, bottom-up
approach. In the growing discipline of Artificial Life, for instance,
an ecosystem is not modeled starting from the whole and dissecting
it into its component parts, but the other way around: one begins
at the bottom, with a population of virtual animals and plants
and their local interactions, and the ecosystem needs to emerge
spontaneously from these local dynamics. The basic idea is that
the systematic properties of an ecosystem arise from the interactions
between its animal and plant components, so that when one dissects
the whole into parts the first thing we lose is any property due
to these interactions. Analytical techniques, by their very nature,
tend to kill emergent properties, that is, properties of the whole
that are more than the sum of its parts. Hence the need for a
more synthetic approach, in which everything systematic about
a given whole is modeled as a historically emergent result of
local interactions. {3}
These new ideas are all the more important when we move on to
the social sciences, particularly economics. In this discipline,
we tend to uncritically assume systematicity, as when one talks
of the "capitalist system", instead of showing exactly
how such systematic properties of the whole emerge from concrete
historical processes. Worse yet, we then tend to reify such unaccounted-for
systematicity, ascribing all kinds of causal powers to capitalism,
to the extent that a clever writer can make it seem as if anything
at all (from nonlinear dynamics itself to postmodernism or cyberculture)
is the product of late capitalism. This basic mistake, which is,
I believe, a major obstacle to a correct understanding of the
nature of economic power, is partly the result of the purely top-down,
analytical style that has dominated economic modeling from the
eighteenth century. Both macroeconomics, which begins at the top
with concepts like gross national product, as well as microeconomics,
in which a system of preferences guides individual choice, are
purely analytical in approach. Neither the properties of a national
economy nor the ranked preferences of consumers are shown to emerge
from historical dynamics. Marxism, is true, added to these models
intermediate scale phenomena, like class struggle, and with it
conflictive dynamics. But the specific way in which it introduced
conflict, via the labor theory of value, has now been shown by
Shraffa to be redundant, added from the top, so to speak, and
not emerging from the bottom, from real struggles over wages, or
the length of the working day, or for control over the production
process. {4}
Besides a switch to a synthetic approach, as it is happening,
for instance, in the evolutionary economics of Nelson and Winter
in which the emphasis is on populations of organizations interacting
nonlinearly, what we need here is a return to the actual details
of economic history. Much has been learned in recent decades about
these details, thanks to the work of materialist historians like
Fernand Braudel, and it is to this historical data that we must
turn to know what we need to model synthetically. Nowhere is this
need for real history more evident that in the subject of the
dynamics of economic power, defined as the capability to manipulate
the prices of inputs and outputs of the production process as
well as their supply and demand. In a peasant market, or even
in a small town local market, everybody involved is a price taker:
one shows up with merchandise, and sells it at the going prices
which reflect demand and supply. But monopolies and oligopolies
are price setters: the prices of their products need not reflect
demand/supply dynamics, but rather their own power to control
a given market share. {5}
When approaching the subject of economic power, one can safely
ignore the entire field of linear mathematical economics (so-called
competitive equilibrium economics), since there monopolies and
oligopolies are basically ignored. Yet, even those thinkers who
make economic power the center of their models, introduce it in
a way that ignores historical facts. Authors writing in the Marxist
tradition, place real history in a straight-jacket by subordinating
it to a model of a progressive succession of modes of production.
Capitalism itself is seen as maturing through a series of stages,
the latest one of which is the monopolistic stage in this century.
Even non-Marxists economists like Galbraith, agree that capitalism
began as a competitive pursuit and stayed that way till the end
of the nineteenth century, and only then it reached the monopolistic
stage, at which point a planning system replaced market dynamics.
However, Fernand Braudel has recently shown, with a wealth of
historical data, that this picture is inherently wrong. Capitalism
was, from its beginnings in the Italy of the thirteenth century,
always monopolistic and oligopolistic. That is to say, the power
of capitalism has always been associated with large enterprises,
large that is, relative to the size of the markets where they
operate. {6} Also, it has always been associated with the ability
to plan economic strategies and to control market dynamics, and
therefore, with a certain degree of centralization and hierarchy.
Within the limits of this presentation, I will not be able to
review the historical evidence that supports this extremely important
hypothesis, but allow me at least to extract some of the consequences
that would follow if it turns out to be true.
First of all, if capitalism has always relied on non-competitive
practices, if the prices for its commodities have never been objectively
set by demand/supply dynamics, but imposed from above by powerful
economic decision-makers, then capitalism and the market have
always been different entities. To use a term introduced by Braudel,
capitalism has always been an "antimarket". This, of
course, would seem to go against the very meaning of the word
"capitalism", regardless of whether the word is used
by Karl Marx or Ronald Reagan. For both nineteenth century radicals
and twentieth century conservatives, capitalism is identified
with an economy driven by market forces, whether one finds this
desirable or not. Today, for example, one speaks of the former
Soviet Union's "transition to a market economy", even
though what was really supposed to happen was a transition to
an antimarket: to large scale enterprises, with several layers
of managerial strata, in which prices are set not taken. This
conceptual confusion is so entrenched that I believe the only
solution is to abandon the term "capitalism" completely,
and to begin speaking of markets and antimarkets and their dynamics.
This would have the added advantage that it would allow us to
get rid of historical theories framed in terms of stages of progress,
and to recognize the fact that antimarkets could have arisen anywhere,
not just Europe, the moment the flows of goods through markets
reach a certain critical level of intensity, so that organizations
bent on manipulating these flows can emerge. Hence, the birth
of antimarkets in Europe has absolutely nothing to do with a peculiarly
European trait, such as rationality or a religious ethic of thrift.
As is well known today, Europe borrowed most of its economic and
accounting techniques, those techniques that are supposed to distinguish
her as uniquely rational, from Islam. {8}
Finally, and before we take a look at what a synthetic, bottom-up
approach to the study of economic dynamics would be like, let
me meet a possible objection to these remarks: the idea that "real"
capitalism did not emerge till the nineteenth century industrial
revolution, and hence that it could not have arisen anywhere else
where these specific conditions did not exist. To criticize this
position, Fernand Braudel has also shown that the idea that capitalism
goes through stages, first commercial, then industrial and finally
financial, is not supported by the available historical evidence.
Venice in the fourteenth century and Amsterdam in the seventeenth,
to cite only two examples, already show the coexistance of the
three modes of capital in interaction. Moreover, other historians
have recently shown that that specific form of industrial production
which we tend to identify as "truly capitalist", that
is, assembly-line mass production, was not born in economic organizations,
but in military ones, beginning in France in the eighteenth century,
and then in the United States in the nineteenth. It was military
arsenals and armories that gave birth to these particularly oppressive
control techniques of the production process, at least a hundred
years before Henry Ford and his Model-T cars {10} Hence, the large firms that make
up the antimarket, can be seen as replicators, much as animals
and plants are. And in populations of such replicators we should
be able to observe the emergence of the different commercial forms,
from the family firm, to the limited liability partnership to
the joint stock company. These three forms, which had already
emerged by the fifteenth century, must be seen as arising, like
those of animals and plants, from slow accumulations of traits
which later become consolidated into more or less permanent structures,
and not, of course, as the manifestation of some pre-existing
essence. In short, both animal and plant species as well as "institutional
species" are historical constructions, the emergence of which
bottom-up models can help us study.
It is important to emphasize that we are not dealing with biological
metaphors here. Any kind of replicating system which produces
variable copies of itself, coupled with any kind of sorting device,
is capable of evolving new forms. This basic insight is now exploited
technologically in the so-called "genetic algorithm",
which allows programmers to breed computer software instead of
painstakingly coding it by hand. A population of computer programs
is allowed to reproduce with some variation, and the programmer
plays the role of sorting device, steering the population towards
the desired form. The same idea is what makes Artificial Life
projects work. Hence, when we say that the forms the antimarket
has taken are evolved historical constructions we do not mean
to say that they are metaphorically like organic forms, but that
they are produced by a process which embodies the same engineering
diagram as the one which generates organic forms. Another example
may help clarify this. When one says, as leftists used to say,
that "class-struggle is the motor of history", one is
using the word "motor" in a metaphorical way. On the
other hand, to say that a hurricane is a steam motor is not to
use the term metaphorically, but literally: one is saying that
the hurricane embodies the same engineering diagram as a steam
motor: it uses a reservoir of heat and operates via differences
of temperature circulated through a Carnot cycle. The same is
true of the genetic algorithm. Anything that replicates, such
as patterns of behavior transmitted by imitation, or rules and
norms transmitted by enforced repetition can give rise to novel
forms, when populations of them are subjected to selection pressures.
And the traits that are thus accumulated can become consolidated
into a permanent structure by codification, as when informal routines
become written rules. {11}
In this case, we have the diagram of a process which generates
hierarchical structures, whether large institutions rigidly controlled
by their rules or organic structures rigidly controlled by their
genes. There are, however, other structure-generating processes
which result in decentralized assemblages of heterogeneous components.
Unlike a species, an ecosystem is not controlled by a genetic
program: it integrates a variety of animals and plants in a food
web, interlocking them together into what has been called a "meshwork
structure". The dynamics of such meshworks are currently
under intense investigation and something like their abstract
diagram is beginning to emerge. {12} From this research, it is
becoming increasingly clear that small markets, that is, local
markets without too many middlemen, embody this diagram: they
allow the assemblage of human beings by interlocking complementary
demands. These markets are indeed, self-organized decentralized
structures: they arise spontaneously without the need for central
planning. As dynamic entities they have absolutely nothing to
do with an "invisible hand", since models based on Adam
Smith's concept operate in a frictionless environment in which
agents have perfect rationality and all information flows freely.
Yet, by eliminating nonlinearities, these models preclude the
spontaneous emergence of order, which depends crucially on friction:
delays, bottlenecks, imperfect decision-making and so on.
The concept of a meshwork can be applied not only to the area
of exchange, but also to that of industrial production. Jane Jacobs
has created a theory of the dynamics of networks of small producers
meshed together by their interdependent functions, and has collected
some historical evidence to support her claims. The basic idea
is that certain relatively backward cities in the past, Venice
when it was still subordinated to Byzantium, or the network New
York-Boston-Philadelphia when still a supply zone for the British
empire, engage in what she calls, import-substitution dynamics.
Because of their subordinated position, they must import most
manufactured products, and export raw materials. Yet, meshworks
of small producers within the city, by interlocking their skills
can begin to replace those imports with local production, which
can then be exchanged with other backward cities. In the process,
new skills and new knowledge is generated, new products begin
to be imported, which in turn, become the raw materials for a
new round of import-substitution. Nonlinear computer simulations
have been created of this process, and they confirm Jacobs' intuition:
a growing meshwork of skills is a necessary condition for urban
morphodynamics. The meshwork as a whole is decentralized, and
it does not grow by planning, but by a kind of creative drift.
{13}
Of course, this dichotomy between command hierarchies and meshworks
should not be taken too rigidly: in reality, once a market grows
beyond a certain size, it spontaneously generates a hierarchy of
exchange, with prestige goods at the top and elementary goods,
like food, at the bottom. Command structures, in turn, generate
meshworks, as when hierarchical organizations created the automobile
and then a meshwork of services (repair shops, gas stations, motels
and so on), grew around it. {14} More importantly, one should
not romantically identify meshworks
with that which is "desirable" or "revolutionary",
since there are situations when they increase the power of hierarchies.
For instance, oligopolistic competition between large firms is
sometimes kept away from price wars by the system of interlocking
directorates, in which representatives of large banks or insurance
companies sit in the boards of directors of these oligopolies.
In this case, a meshwork of hierarchies is almost equivalent to
a monopoly. {15} And yet, however complex the interaction between
hierarchies and meshworks, the distinction is real: the former
create structures out of elements sorted out into homogenous ranks,
the latter articulates heterogeneous elements as such, without
homogenization. A bottom-up approach to economic modeling should
represent institutions as varying mixtures of command and market
components, perhaps in the form of combinations of negative feedback
loops, which are homogenizing, and positive feedback, which generates
heterogeneity.
What would one expect to emerge from such populations of more
or less centralized organizations and more or less decentralized
markets? The answer is, a world-economy, or a large zone of economic
coherence. The term, which should not be confused with that of
a global economy, was coined by Immanuel Wallerstein, and later
adapted by Braudel so as not to depend on a conception of history
in terms of a unilineal progression of modes of production. From
Wallerstein Braudel takes the spatial definition of a world-economy:
an economically autonomous portion of the planet, perhaps coexisting
with other such regions, with a definite geographical structure:
a core of cities which dominate it, surrounded by yet other economically
active cities subordinated to the core and forming a middle zone,
and finally a periphery of completely exploited supply zones. The
role of core of the European world-economy has been historically
played by several cities: first Venice in the fourteenth century,
followed by Antwerp and Genoa in the fifteenth and sixteenth.
Amsterdam then dominated it for the next two centuries, followed
by London and then New York. Today, we may be witnessing the end
of American supremacy and the role of core seems to be moving
to Tokyo. {16}
Interestingly, those cities which play the role of core, seem
to generate in their populations of firms, very few large ones.
For instance, when Venice played this role, no large organizations
emerged in it, even though they already existed in nearby Florence.
Does this contradict the thesis that capitalism has always been
monopolistic? I think not. What happens is that, in this case,
Venice as a whole played the role of a monopoly: it completely
controlled access to the spice and luxury markets in the Levant.
Within Venice, everything seemed like "free competition",
and yet its rich merchants enjoyed tremendous advantages over
any foreign rival, whatever its size. Perhaps this can help explain
the impression classical economists had of a competitive stage
of capitalism: when the Dutch or the British advocated "free
competition" internally is precisely when their cities as
a whole held a virtual monopoly on world trade.
World-economies, then, present a pattern of concentric circles
around a center, defined by relations of subordination. Besides
this spatial structure, Wallerstein and Braudel add a temporal
one: a world-economy expands and contracts in a variety of rhythms
of different lengths: from short term business cycles to longer
term Kondratiev cycles which last approximately fifty years.
While the domination by core cities gives a world-economy its
spatial unity, these cycles give it a temporal coherence: prices
and wages move in unison over the entire area. Prices are, of
course, much higher at the center than at the periphery, and this
makes everything flow towards the core: Venice, Amsterdam, London
and New York, as they took their turn as dominant centers, became
"universal warehouses" where one could find any product
from anywhere in the world. And yet, while respecting these differences,
all prices moved up and down following these nonlinear rhythms,
affecting even those firms belonging to the antimarket, which
needed to consider those fluctuations when setting their own prices.
These self-organized patterns in time and space which define world-economies
were first discovered in analytical studies of historical data.
The next step is to use synthetic techniques and create the conditions
under which they can emerge in our models. In fact, bottom-up
computer simulations of urban economics where spatial and temporal
patterns spontaneously emerge already exist. For example, Peter
Allen has created simulations of nonlinear urban dynamics as meshworks
of interdependent economic functions. Unlike earlier mathematical
models of the distribution of urban centers, which assumed perfect
rationality on the part of economic agents, and where spatial
patterns resulted from the optimal use of some resource such as
transportation, here patterns emerge from a dynamic of conflict
and cooperation. As the flows of goods, services and people in
and out of these cities change, some urban centers grow while
others decay. Stable patterns of coexisting centers arise as bifurcations
occur in the growing city networks taking them from attractor to
attractor. {17}
Something like Allen's approach would be useful to model one of
the two things that stitch world-economies together, according
to Braudel: trade circuits. However, to generate the actual spatial
patterns that we observe in the history of Europe, we need to
include the creation of chains of subordination among these cities,
of hierarchies of dependencies besides the meshworks of interdependencies.
This would need the inclusion of monopolies and oligopolies,
growing out of each cities meshworks of small producers and traders.
We would also need to model the extensive networks of merchants
and bankers with which dominant cities invaded their surrounding
urban centers, converting them into a middle zone at the service
of the core. A dynamical system of trade circuits, animated by
import-substitution dynamics within each city, and networks of
merchants extending the reach of large firms of each city, may
be able to give us some insight into the real historical dynamics
of the European economy. {18}
Bottom-up economic models which generate temporal patterns have
also been created. One of the most complex simulations in this
area is the Systems Dynamics National Model at MIT. Unlike econometric
simulations, where one begins at the macroeconomic level, this
one is built up from the operating structure within corporations.
Production processes within each industrial sector are modeled
in detail. The decision-making behind price setting, for instance,
is modeled using the know-how from real managers. The model includes
many nonlinearities normally dismissed in classical economic models,
like delays, bottlenecks and the inevitable friction due to bounded
rationality. The simulation was not created with the purpose of
confirming the existence of the Kondratiev wave, the fifty-two
year cycle that can be observed in the history of wholesale prices
for at least two centuries. In fact, the designers of the model
were unaware of the literature on the subject. Yet, when the simulation
began to unfold, it reached a bifurcation and a periodic attractor
emerged in the system, which began pulsing to a fifty year beat.
The crucial element in this dynamics seems to be the capital goods
sector, the part of the industry that creates the machines that
the rest of the economy uses. Whenever an intense rise in global
demand occurs, firms need to expand and so need to order new machines.
But when the capital goods sector in turn expands to meet this
demand it needs to order from itself. This creates a positive
feedback loop that pushes the system towards a bifurcation. {19}
Insights coming from running simulations like these can, in turn,
be used to build other simulations and to suggest directions for
historical research to follow. We can imagine parallel computers
in the near future running simulations combining all the insights
from the ones we just discussed: spatial networks of cities, breathing
at different rhythms, and housing evolving populations of organizations
and meshworks of interdependent skills. If power relations are
included, monopolies and oligopolies will emerge and we will be
able to explore the genesis and evolution of the antimarket. If
we include the interactions between different forms of organizations,
then the relationships between economic and military institutions
may be studied. As Galbraith has pointed out, in today's economy
nothing goes against the market, nothing is a better representative
of the planning system, as he calls it, than the military-industrial
complex. {20} But we would be wrong in thinking that this is a
modern phenomenon, something caused by "late capitalism".
In the first core of the European world-economy, thirteenth century
Venice, the alliance between monopoly power and military might
was already in evidence. The Venetian arsenal, where all the merchant
ships were built, was the largest industrial complex of its time.
We can think of these ships as the fixed capital, the productive
machinery of Venice, since they were used to do all the trade
that kept her powerful; but at the same time, they were military
machines used to enforce her monopolistic practices. {21} When
the turn of Amsterdam and London came to be the core, the famous
Companies of Indias with which they conquered the Asian world-economy,
transforming it into a periphery of Europe, were also hybrid military-economic
institutions. We have already mentioned the role that French armories
and arsenals in the eighteenth century, and American ones in the
nineteenth, played in the birth of mass production techniques.
Frederick Taylor, the creator of the modern system for the control
the labor process, learned his craft in military arsenals. That
nineteenth century radical economists did not understand this
hybrid nature of the antimarket can be seen from the fact that
Lenin himself welcomed Taylorism into revolutionary Russia as
a progressive force, instead of seeing for what it was: the imposition
of a rigid command-hierarchy on the workplace. {22}
Unlike these thinkers, we should include in our simulations all
the institutional interactions that historians have uncovered,
to correctly model the hybrid economic-military structure of the
antimarket. Perhaps by using these synthetic models as tools of
exploration, as intuition synthesizers, so to speak, we will also
be able to study the feasibility of counteracting the growth of
the antimarket by a proliferation of meshworks of small producers.
Multinational corporations, according to the influential theory
of "transaction-costs", grow by swallowing up meshworks,
by internalizing markets either through vertical or horizontal
integration. {23} They can do this thanks to their enormous economic
power (most of them are oligopolies), and to their having access
to intense economies of scale. However, meshworks of small producers
interconnected via computer networks could have access to different,
yet as intense economies of scale. A well studied example is the
symbiotic collection of small textile firms that has emerged in
an Italian region between Bologna and Venice. The operation of
a few centralized textile corporations was broken down into a
decentralized network of firms, in which entrepreneurs replace
managers and short runs of specialized products replace large
run of mass produced ones. Computer networks allow these small
firms to react flexibly to sudden shifts in demand, so that no
firm becomes overloaded while others sit idly with spare capacity.
{24}
But more importantly, a growing pool of skills is thereby created,
and because this pool has not been internalized by a large corporation,
it can not be taken away. Hence this region will not suffer the
fate of so many American company towns, which die after the corporation
that feeds them moves elsewhere. This self-organized reservoirs
of skills also explain why economic development cannot be exported
to the third world via large transfers of capital invested in dams
or other large structures. Economic development must emerge from
within as meshworks of skills grow and proliferate. {25} Computer
networks are an important element here, since the savings in coordination
costs that multinational corporations achieve by internalizing
markets, can be enjoyed by small firms through the use of decentralizing
technology. Computers may also help us to create a new approach
to control within these small firms. The management approach used
by large corporations was in fact developed during World War II
under the name of Operations Research. Much as mass production
techniques effected a transfer of a command hierarchy from military
arsenals to civilian factories, management practices based on
linear analysis carry with them the centralizing tendencies of
the military institutions where they were born. Fresh approaches
to these questions are now under development by nonlinear scientists,
in which the role of managers is not to impose preconceived plans
on workers, but to catalyze the emergence of meshworks of decision-making
processes among them. {26} Computers, in the form of embedded intelligence in the buildings that house small firms, can aid
this catalytic process, allowing the firm's members to reach
some measure of self-organization. Although these efforts are
in their infancy, they may one day play a crucial role in adding
some heterogeneity to a world-economy that's becoming increasingly
homogenized.
FOOTNOTES:
{1} Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers. Order out of Chaos.
(Bantam Books, New York 1984). p.169.
{2} Stuart A. Kauffman. The Origins of Order. Self Organization
and Selection in Evolution.
(Oxford Univ. Press, New York 1993) p.280
{3} Christopher G. Langton. Artificial Life. In C.G. Langton
ed. Artificial Life. (Addison-Wesley, 1989) p.2
{4} Geoff Hodgson. Critique of Wright 1: Labour and Profits.
In
Ian Steedman ed. The Value Controversy.
(Verso, London 1981). p.93
{5} John Keneth Galbraith. The New Industrial State.
(Houghton Mifflin, Boston 1978) p.24
{6} Fernand Braudel. Civilization and Capitalism, 15th-18th
Century. Vol 2. (Harper and Row, New York 1982) p.229
{8} William H. McNeill. The Pursuit of Power.
(University of Chicago Press, 1982) p.49
{9} Merrit Roe Smith. Army Ordnance and the "American system"
of Manufacturing, 1815-1861. In M.R.Smith ed. Military
Enterprise and Technological Change.
(MIT Press, 1987) p.47
{10} Richard Nelson and Sidney Winter. An Evolutionary Theory
of Economic Change. (Belknap Press, Cambridge Mass 1982) p.98
{11} Richard Dawkins. The Selfish Gene.
(Oxford University Press, New York 1989) ch.11
{12} Stuart Kauffman. The Evolution of Economic Webs. In Philip
Anderson, Kenneth Arrow and David Pines eds. The Economy as
an Evolving Complex System. (Addison-Wesley, 1988)
{13} Jane Jacobs. Cities and the Wealth of Nations.
(Random House, New York 1984) p.133
{14} The dichotomy Meshwork/Hierarchy is a special case of what
Deleuze and Guattari call Smooth/Striated or Rhizome/Tree.
Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari. 1440: The Smooth and the
Striated. In A Thousand Plateaus.
(University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis 1987) ch.14
{15} John R. Munkirs and James I. Sturgeon. Oligopolistic
Cooperation: Conceptual and Empirical Evidence of Market
Structure Evolution. In Marc. R. Tool and Warren J. Samuels
eds. The Economy as a System of Power.
(Transaction Press, New Brunswick 1989). p.343
{16} Fernand Braudel. op. cit. Vol 3. p.25-38
{17} Peter M. Allen. Self-Organization in the Urban System.
In William C. Schieve and P.M.Allen eds. Self-Organization
and Dissipative Structures: Applications in the Physical and
the Social Sciences.
(University of Texas, Austin 1982) p.136
{18} Fernand Braudel. op. cit. Vol 3. p.140-167
{19} J.D. Sterman. Nonlinear Dynamics in the World Economy: the
Economic Long Wave. In Peter Christiansen and R.D. Parmentier
eds. Structure, Coherence and Chaos in Dynamical Systems.
(Manchester Univ. Press, Manchester 1989)
{20} John Galbraith. op. cit. p. 321
{21} Fernand Braudel. op. cit. Vol 2 p. 444
{22} Vladimir Lenin. The Immediate Tests of the Soviet Goverment.
Collected Works, Vol 27 (Moskow 1965).
{23} Jean-Francois Hennart. The Transaction Cost Theory of the
Multinational Enterprise. In Christos Pitelis and Roger
Sudgen eds. The Nature of the Transnational Firm.
(Rutledge, London 1991).
{24} Thomas W. Malone and John F. Rockart. Computers, Networks
and the Corporation.
In Scientific American Vol 265 Number 3 p.131
Also:
Jane Jacobs, op. cit. p.40
Fernand Braudel, op cit Vol 3 p. 630
{25} Jane Jacobs. op. cit. p.148
{26} F. Malik and G. Probst. Evolutionary Management.
In H.Ulrich and G. Probst eds. Self-Organization and
Management of Social Systems.
(Springer Verlag, Berlin 1984) p. 113